throbber
Anticipation and the Valuation of Delayed Consumption
`Author(s): George Loewenstein
`Source: The Economic Journal, Vol. 97, No. 387 (Sep., 1987), pp. 666-684
`Published by: Blackwell Publishing for the Royal Economic Society
`Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2232929
`Accessed: 18/07/2009 10:18
`
`Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
`http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
`you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
`may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.
`
`Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at
`http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=black.
`
`Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
`page of such transmission.
`
`JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the
`scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that
`promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
`
`Royal Economic Society and Blackwell Publishing are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and
`extend access to The Economic Journal.
`
`http://www.jstor.org
`
`IPR2020-00963
`Sony EX1011 Page 1
`
`

`

`The Economic Journal, 97 (September I987), 666-684
`Printed in Great Britain
`
`AND THE VALUATION
`ANTICIPATION
`OF DELAYED CONSUMPTION*
`
`George Loewenstein
`
`'When calculating the rate at whic-h a future benefit is discounted, we must
`be careful to make allowance for the pleasures of expectation.' (Marshall,
`i89i, p. I78)
`Of the various assumptions underlying analyses of intertemporal choice,
`perhaps the assumption of positive discounting is the most widespread and
`noncontroversial. Empirical work which has sought to estimate individual
`discount rates (Hausman, I979; Landsberger, I971) has provided no grounds
`for questioning this assumption. In fact, a recent study which explicitly
`questioned the general applicability of positive discounting concluded that 'the
`case for positive time preference is absolutely compelling' (Olson and Bailey,
`I 98 I).
`Yet it requires little effort to think of examples of behaviour in which negative
`discounting is apparent. The pleasurable deferral of a vacation, the speeding
`up of a dental appointment, the prolonged storage of a bottle of expensive
`champagne are all instances of this phenomenon. Indeed, if R. H. Strotz had
`begun his work thirty years ago with behaviour such as this in mind, he might
`have developed a critique of Discounted Utility theory (DU) equally as
`compelling as his work on myopia but pointing towards research very different
`from what has actually ensued from his work. Instead, in introducing the broad
`concept of 'time inconsistency', Strotz devoted his attention exclusively to a
`subdomain of instances in which the economic actor behaves more myopically
`in the present than he previously had planned. While the focus on impulsivity
`has offered important theoretical insights it may have impeded recognition of
`the existence and interest of other phenomena, such as low or negative
`discounting. A more inclusive theory of intertemporal choice should be able to
`account for both extremes of behaviour - myopic and far-sighted. Such a
`model is proposed here.
`The model modifies DU by introducing an insight once recognised by
`economists: that anticipation of the future has an impact on immediate
`well-being.1 This observation can be traced to Bentham (I789), who included
`among the ingredients of utility, pleasures and pains that derive from antici-
`pation. For Bentham, anticipation, like consumption itself, was an important
`source of pleasure and pain.
`
`* I thank Robert Abelson, Richard Levin, Sidney Winter,John Geanakoplos, Howard Kunreuther, Colin
`Camerer, Mark Machina and Robin Pope for their helpful suggestions. The support of the Institute for
`Advanced Study, in Princeton. is gratefullv acknowledged.
`1 In exploring the relationship between anticipation and time discounting, the current paper is akin to
`the recent work of Pope (1983), who examined the role of anticipation in risk aversion, and Wolf (1970),
`who discussed the implications for intertemporal choice of utility from memory.
`[ 666 ]
`
`IPR2020-00963
`Sony EX1011 Page 2
`
`

`

`667
`OF DELAYED
`VALUATION
`CONSUMPTION
`i987]
`[SEPT.
`Jevons who was one of the first to apply the Benthamite concept of utility
`to understanding intertemporal trade-offs, wrote: 'Three distinct ways are
`recognisable in which pleasurable or painful feelings are caused:
`(I) By the memory of past events;
`(2) By the sensation of present events;
`(3) By anticipation of future events.' (I905, p. 3)
`The latter, which Jevons termed 'anticipal pleasure' and 'anticipal pain'
`were, if anything, the most important for understanding economic behaviour:
`'The science of economics is very largely occupied in studying man's efforts to
`obtain anticipal pleasure by the provision of stocks of goods for future use:
`almost all the complicated practices of production and exchange resolve
`themselves ultimately into manifestations of these efforts' (I 905, p. 65) . In what
`follows, the term 'savouring' refers to positive utility derived from anticipation
`of future consumption; 'dread' refers to negative utility resulting from con-
`templation of the future.
`
`STUDY
`I. AN ILLUSTRATIVE
`Fig. I summarises results from a survey in which 30 undergraduates were asked
`to specify the 'most you would pay now' to obtain (avoid) each of five outcomes,
`immediately, and following five different time delays. The outcomes were: (i)
`obtain four dollars; (2) avoid losing four dollars; (3) avoid losing one thousand
`
`2 0 -
`
`(D 1*5-
`
`4-
`0
`
`0
`
`0
`v:
`0
`
`1.0
`
`0
`
`0 5
`
`Shock/
`
`~~~~~~~~Lose
`$1000
`
`Lose $4
`
`Gain $4
`
`Immediately 3 hours
`
`3 days
`24 hours
`Time delay
`
`1 year
`
`10 years
`
`Fig. i. Maximum payment to obtain/avoid outcomes at selected times. Proportion of current
`value (N= 30).
`
`dollars; (4) avoid receiving a (non-lethal) one hundred and ten volt shock, and
`(5) obtain a kiss from the movie star of your choice. Time delays were: (i)
`immediately (no delay); (2) in twenty-four hours; (3) in three days; (4) in one
`year; (5) in ten years. Subjects were asked to specify the most they would pay
`
`IPR2020-00963
`Sony EX1011 Page 3
`
`

`

`668
`[SEPTEMBER
`JOURNAL
`THE ECONOMIC
`for every combination of outcome and time delay. They were told to assume
`that all outcomes were certain to occur at the designated time. Summary
`statistics for the study are presented in Appeindix i.
`It can be seen that the two non-monetary items, the kiss and the shock, both
`exhibit unusual patterns of devaluation. DU, with positive discounting, predicts
`that people will prefer to consume desired outcomes as soon as possible. This
`prediction is contradicted by the kiss item. Subjects on average were willing
`to pay more to experience a kiss delayed by 3 days than an immediate kiss or
`one delayed by three hours or one day. Data presented later in this paper show
`that the hump-shaped pattern of devaluation evident in Fig. i is common for
`desirable consumption that is fleeting.
`Likewise, DU asserts that people prefer to delay undesirable outcomes
`whenever possible. The shock item contrasts sharply with this prediction.
`Subjects were, on average, willing to pay slightly more to avoid a shock that
`was delayed for 3 hours to 3 days than to avoid an immediate shock. They were
`willing to pay substantially more to avoid a shock delayed by one or ten years.
`In contrast to the patterns of responses for the kiss and shock, the money
`amounts included in the survey appear to be discounted in the normal fashion.
`Why haven't patterns of intertemporal preference such as those exhibited
`towards the kiss and shock appeared in earlier empirical work on intertemporal
`choice? Several answers are possible. In some cases, economists have attempted
`to infer intertemporal preferences from behaviour in which such preferences
`were irrelevant to behaviour. Hausman's attempt to estimate individual
`discount rates from air-conditioner purchases provides an example. Air con-
`ditioners vary in purchase price and energy efficiency, thus creating a choice
`between immediate versus deferred payments. Hausman, by observing the
`price/efficiency rating of a purchased air-conditioner, attempted to impute the
`discount rate of the purchaser. The problem with this approach is that
`individual discount rates should be irrelevant to what model is purchased. If
`consumers are able to save and dissave (or borrow) at established interest rates,
`they should logically purchase the model of air conditioner that minimises at
`the desired level of cooling capacity, the net present value of the time stream
`of payments.2 Similar considerations may have caused subjects in the current
`experiment to discount the money amounts in a conventional manner, in
`contrast to their behaviour towards the kiss and shock.
`In other cases, economists have attempted to estimate discount rate from
`individual saving behaviour, but such attempts are even more problematic since
`individuals have little influence on interest rates. The interest rate at which an
`individual saves or borrows gives no information about his or her own discount
`rate and hence it is necessary to infer discount rates from level or rate of saving,
`a process that is extremely sensitive to the specification of the model used to
`represent the savings decision. Furthermore, savings behaviour depends on so
`many factors other than discount rates (e.g. expected future income streams,
`
`2 His finding of substantial differences in discounting between different income groups suggests either that
`unobserved economic factors such as liquidity constraints were operative, or that consumers were failing to
`behave rationally.
`
`IPR2020-00963
`Sony EX1011 Page 4
`
`

`

`669
`i987]
`CONSUMPTION
`OF DELAYED
`VALUATION
`projected needs) that it is exceedingly difficult to isolate the effect of time
`preference on saving.
`In this paper it is argued that patterns of preference such as those exhibited
`towards the kiss and shock, and other DU anomalies discussed below, can be
`explained by incorporating Jevons' anticipal pleasure and pain into an
`otherwise standard model of intertemporal choice. In what follows, such a
`model is developed in the simplest possible terms, and its implications are
`discussed.
`
`II. THE MODEL
`The following model explores the question of how an individual values a single
`future act of consumption under conditions of certainty. The model depicts a
`consumer at time to who anticipates consuming x at time T > to. Consumption
`is assumed to yield a constant stream of utility, U(x), beginning at time T and
`continuing for duration L, after which it drops to zero. Formally:
`for T < t < T+L,
`Utf(X, T, L) = U(x)
`= o otherwise
`where Ut, indicates utility experienced at time t from consumption.
`At any time t between to and T (when consumption begins) the individual
`derives utility from anticipation, UtA. Utility from articipation is assumed to
`be proportional to the integral of utility from consumption discounted at a rate
`of 6. 6 is not the conventional discount rate, but a measure of the degree to
`which the individual derives immediate utility from anticipated consumption.
`Thus savouring or dread at each point t is equal to:
`r T+L
`
`(I)
`
`-
`
`U(x) e-8(T-t)
`
`(I -eaL).
`
`This formulation has four desirable properties discussed by Jevons in his
`enumeration of the laws of anticipal pleasure and pain. Referring to anticipation
`of a planned vacation, Jevons wrote:
`The intensity of the anticipation will be greater the longer the holiday;
`greater also, the more intensely one expects to enjoy it when the time
`comes. In other words the amount of pleasure expected is one factor
`determining the intensity of anticipal pleasure. Again, the nearer the date
`fixed for leaving home approaches, the greater does the intensity of
`anticipal pleasure become: at first when the holiday is still many weeks
`ahead, the intensity increases slowly; then, as the time grows closer, it
`increases faster and faster, until it culminates on the eve of departure
`(I905, p- 64).
`In the current formulation, as Jevons proposed, utility from anticipation,
`UtA, is a positive function of L, the duration of consumption, a positive function
`
`UtA(x, T,L) =
`
`6e-f(T-t) U(x) dT
`e
`
`T
`
`(2)
`
`(3)
`
`IPR2020-00963
`Sony EX1011 Page 5
`
`

`

`670
`[SEPTEMBER
`JOURNAL
`THE ECONOMIC
`of U(x), the utility that will be derived from consumption, and a negative
`the time delay prior to consumption. Also, the second
`function of (T-t),
`derivative of UA with respect to ( T- t) is positive, yielding the accelerating path
`of utility from anticipation suggested by Jevons.
`Fig. 2 depicts one possible time path of utility from anticipation and
`consumption.
`
`to
`
`T
`
`T+L
`
`Fig. 2. Utility from anticipation and consumption.
`
`The individual is assumed to evaluate a delayed act of consumption
`according to the integral of discounted utility from anticipation and consump-
`tion that it yields. Thus, the present value Y (measured in dollars) ofa delayed act of
`consumption is defined by:
`
`(i -e-8L)
`
`U(x) e-r(t-to) dt,
`
`(4)
`
`e-r(t-to) dt + J
`
`T+L
`
`CT C
`U( Y) = J X U(x) e-8(T-t)
`utility from
`utility from
`consumption
`anticipation
`where r is the conventional discount rate used to discount future utility from
`all sources and U(Y) is a 'ratio scale' utility function3 with positive first and
`negative second derivative. Throughout the following, r is assumed to be
`positive.
`Setting to = o for simplicity, and integrating:
`
`U(Y) = U(X)[8
`
`(e-rTe-T)
`
`( -e
`
`r e
`
`(i -rL
`
`(5)
`
`& and oc define to the relationship between UA and UC. 6 is a measure of an
`individual's preoccupation with the future. Someone with a low a savours or
`dreads even those outcomes that will occur in the distant future. a is a measure
`of the 'imaginability' or 'vividness' of a particular outcome. Factors that raise
`a or lower a increase utility from savouring or dread. (A later section discusses
`attempts on the part of marketers and policy makers to influence cz.) Since most
`people take account of future outcomes (e.g. save for their retirement) even
`when they do not immediately savour or dread those outcomes, it is assumed
`that & > r.
`
`III. IMPLICATIONS OF THE MODEL
`The model, as it stands, suggests the conditions under which people will prefer
`to delay desired consumption or get undesirable consumption over with quickly.
`These two cases are explored in turn.
`invariant with respect to multiplicative transformations.
`
`3I.e.
`
`IPR2020-00963
`Sony EX1011 Page 6
`
`

`

`I987]
`
`VALUATION
`
`OF DELAYED
`
`CONSUMPTION
`
`67I
`
`Delaying of Desired Consumption
`Desired consumption will be delayed when (8Y/IT) > o i.e. when the net
`present value of consumption, taking account of both savouring and consump-
`tion itself, increases as a function of time delay. Since U(Y) is monotonically
`increasing, this condition is equivalent to 8U(Y)/8 T> o.
`Differentiating (5) with respect to T:
`
`er(y = U(X [(_)
`
`(4e-11- re-ril) (i -e-1L-1-e-rT (i- e-rL)
`
`(6)
`
`The first term in the brackets is the marginal benefit from savouring,
`that would be gained from delaying. The second term is the marginal cost of
`delay, in terms of increased discounting of consumption.
`Consumption will be deferred when 8U(Y) /D T is positive for T = o. Setting
`T = o:
`
`au(Y)
`= U(x)
`A T T=o0
`A necessary and sufficient condition for delaying desired consumption is,
`therefore,
`t
`
`a
`
`(I-e-L)
`
`- U(x) (I - e-rL).
`
`(7)
`
`(8)
`
`(I-e-L)
`
`>
`
`i-e-rL.
`
`As would be expected, delaying is more likely when a is large and a is small.
`Fig. 3 illustrates the relationship between Y, the net present value of
`consumption and T, the time at which consumption of x begins, for the case
`when (8Y/I T) is initially positive.
`
`co
`
`z
`
`to
`Fig. 3. Value at time to of an outcome to be consumed at time T.
`
`T: time consumption begins
`
`Tm
`
`By reading off the net present value of consumption at any point T on Fig.
`3, and subtracting it from one, it is possible to derive a crude measure of the
`value of consumption of x at time T relative to the value of immediate
`consumption of x. Note that such 'devaluing' (negative or positive) of
`consumption as a function of delay must be distinguished from the individual's
`discounting of future utility, which is based only on r(.). To avoid confusion
`between these concepts a distinction is henceforth drawn between 'discounting',
`which refers to a preference for early over later utility, and 'devaluing', which
`refers to a decrease in the outcome's value at time to as a function of delay.
`'Devaluing' is also synonymous with the rate of time discount which would
`
`IPR2020-00963
`Sony EX1011 Page 7
`
`

`

`672
`[SEPTEMBER
`JOURNAL
`THE ECONOMIC
`be estimated by an observer who did not take account of utility from
`anticipation. In Fig. 3, it can be seen, devaluing is initially negative and only
`eventually becomes positive even though time preference is always positive - i.e.
`r > o.
`Point T. in Fig. 3 has special significance. Tm is, for desirable outcomes, the
`individual's most preferred time of consumption. Tm will be greater than to if
`(8 Y/I T) is positive for T= o (condition 8). When condition 8 is met it will
`also be the case that (82Y/I T2) < o, ensuring that the point T. is a maximum
`(see Appendix 2). Under the standard approach (in the absence of planning
`or scarcity effects), T. is always equal to to. T. > to thus constitutes a sharp
`distinction between the predictions of the current model and the standard DU
`approach.
`
`Conditions Conducive to Delaying of Desired Consumption
`By totally differentiating (6) (see Appendix 3), it is possible to derive proposit-
`ions regarding the effect on Tm of changes in the different parameters of the
`model.
`Increasing the duration of consumption, L, raises the marginal cost of
`deferring at Tm more than it increases the marginal benefit of savouring.
`Therefore, increasing L discourages delaying behaviour (8 Tm/IL < o). Con-
`versely, delaying is more likely when consumption is fleeting. Intuitively this seems
`plausible. Those forms of consumption that are commonly delayed typically
`provide brief but intense pleasure. In such cases anticipation (and sometimes
`memory) serves to extend the otherwise fleeting benefit provided by
`consumption.
`Raising a, as would be expected, also encourages delaying behaviour. a, for
`desirable outcomes, can be viewed as a measure of the 'savourability' of
`consumption. Outcomes that can be readily imagined and that are pleasurable
`to contemplate are therefore more likely to be delayed. The effect of changes in
`a on Tm is ambiguous.
`The 'kiss from the movie star of your choice' in the study was chosen for its
`fleeting quality and high degree of 'savourability', characteristics which are
`predicted to promote delay. It was also chosen to rule out, as much as possible,
`alternative explanations for delaying behaviour. Two such explanations are
`worthy of note. The first, the 'planning effect', provides an incentive for delay
`when, by delaying a desired outcome, preparations can be made that will
`enhance utility from consumption. This is certainly true of food consumption,
`in which case fasting (within limits) enhances pleasure from subsequent eating.
`In the case of the kiss it also seems reasonable to assume that some preparations
`(such as gargling, or moving to a dimly lit room) could intensify the experience.
`But it is difficult to see how a delay of three days, which was generally preferred
`to a single-day delay, could add much to such preparations.
`The second alternative explanation for delaying is the 'scarcity effect'. The
`basis of this argument is that some items are scarcer in the future (e.g.
`raspberries in winter) than they are in the present and thus should be more
`highly valued. The kiss from a movie star of your choice, which is a scarce item
`
`IPR2020-00963
`Sony EX1011 Page 8
`
`

`

`673
`I987]
`CONSUMPTION
`OF DELAYED
`VALUATION
`at any time and certainly as scarce in three days as at the present moment, was
`chosen to avoid this alternative explanation.
`Accelerating Undesirable Consumption
`The shape of Uto( T) for an undesirable outcome, which is a negative reflection
`of its shape for desirable outcomes, is shown in Fig. 4. In the case of undesirable
`outcomes a different point, Ti, has behavioural significance. Ti is the point at
`which an individual is indifferent between immediate and deferred consump-
`tion. If allowed to defer a negative outcome beyond Ti, the individual will do
`so. If constrained to consume x prior to 7i, however, his preferences will be
`reversed, and he will prefer to get x over with immediately. A common example
`of such behaviour is associated with medical or dental treatment. One puts off
`visiting the doctor or dentist as long as possible, but once a maximum delay
`is imposed - e.g., when one receives a card in the mail urging a visit - typically
`one asks for the first available appointment. Under the standard approach Ti
`always equals t0.
`
`T: time consumption begins
`
`to
`
`0
`
`;O.
`
`E 1-
`0.
`
`z
`
`T,
`I
`
`? --1___
`
`Fig. 4. Value at time to of consumption at time T.
`
`Equation (g) defines Ti.
`
`(
`
`- (erL)
`
`- U(X)
`
`) (e-rT
`
`(I-e-L)
`
`+ U(x)- erTi
`
`-e-rL)
`
`(9)
`
`The left-hand side of (g) represents the (negative) utility that would be
`experienced if x were consumed beginning immediately. The right-hand side
`expresses discounted utility (from dread and consumption) when consumption
`is delayed until T7 > to. When these expressions are equal, the individual at to
`is indifferent between consuming immediately or at Ti. If constrained to
`consume at any point prior to 7i, he would prefer to consume immediately.
`Again we are interested in the specific conditions that encourage individuals
`to get unpleasant outcomes over with quickly - i.e. make T > to. These
`conditions turn out to be analogous to those for Tm (see Appendix 4). The more
`fleeting an undesirable outcome - i.e. the shorter L - the greater is the tendency
`to get consumption over with quickly. People should therefore be especially
`likely to get fleeting outcomes over with quickly and defer those for which
`consumption is prolonged. This has the sensible implication that people will
`always defer outcomes whose effects are prolonged or permanent, e.g. loss of
`
`IPR2020-00963
`Sony EX1011 Page 9
`
`

`

`674
`THE ECONOMIC
`JOURNAL
`[SEPTEMBER
`a leg. It is also the case that 8 7i/8a > o; people are likely to get those outcomes
`over with quickly that can be vividly imagined beforehand.
`Thus we should expect that the tendency to get unpleasant outcomes over
`with quickly will be greatest for outcomes that are fleeting and vivid. The shock
`item in the study was chosen to have these characteristics. Lest the survey results,
`which involve hypothetical responses, be questioned, it should be noted that
`several other studies involving real shocks produced similar results (Carlsmith,
`In fact even rats, in one experiment, when
`I962; Barnes and Barnes, I964).
`faced with a choice between an immediate or moderately delayed shock, tended
`to choose the immediate shock (Knapp et al. I 959). Furthermore, when rats are
`exposed to delayed shocks they typically exhibit physiological signs of fear such
`as elevated heartbeat and blood pressure while they wait, suggesting that fear
`may be a motivating factor in the choice of the immediate shock.
`A problem with the use of the shock item is that it is difficult to generalise
`the findings to economic behaviour in naturalistic settings. This particular
`problem is avoided in subsequent research in which subjects were asked among
`other questions: 'What is the least amount of money you would accept for
`cleaning i OO hamster cages at the Psychology Department's animal laboratory.
`You will be paid the money immediately. You should be willing to do the job
`for the amount you specify but not if you were offered only one dollar less. The
`job is unpleasant but takes only 3 hours. How much would you need to be paid
`to clean the cages: (i) once during the next 7 days; (2) once during the week
`beginning two months from today; (3) once during the week beginning one year
`from now?'
`The mean reservation wage for cage cleaning in the following week was $30
`(standard error 3 i). For cleaning the cage in a year respondents required an
`average of $37 in immediate payment (standard error 3-8). In fact, of 37
`respondents only 2 gave a smaller response to question (3) than to question (i)!
`
`Positive Devaluation
`When condition (8) is not met - i.e. for consumption that is lasting, or if a is
`small - we should not expect to observe negative devaluing. Nevertheless, utility
`from anticipation will still affect the devaluation of consumption. Fig. 5
`illustrates the effect of variations in L on devaluation of future consumption.
`Decreasing L will attenuate devaluing, flatten the slope 8U, /8 T and thus
`(see Appendix 5, which demonstrates that 82Y/ITOL < o). As L
`8Y/IT
`increases, therefore, Y(T) will lose its hump and will begin to take on the
`
`> 1- G
`a)
`
`X~~~Fleeting
`c~~~~~onsumption
`
`e)
`
`Prolonged
`consumption
`
`T: time of consumption
`
`Fig. 5.
`
`IPR2020-00963
`Sony EX1011 Page 10
`
`

`

`675
`I987]
`OF DELAYED
`CONSUMPTION
`VALUATION
`reversed 'S' shape depicted in Fig. 5. Savouring, even when it does not cause
`devaluing to be negative, attenuates devaluing for small delays, bridging the
`gap between sporadic or short-lived consumption and pleasure of ownership.
`
`IMPLICATIONS
`
`IV. ECONOMIC
`Attempts to Manipulate a,
`The concept of 'vividness' or imaginability embodied in the a term played a
`central role in historical formulations of intertemporal choice. For example,
`Bohm-Bawerk cited 'the fragmentary nature of the imaginary picture that we
`construct of the future state of our works' (I889, p. 269) first in his list of causes
`for the systematic tendency to undervalue future wants. Marshall noted that
`a person's willingness ... to wait depends on his habit of vividly realising the
`future' (I89I, p. 293). Although modern accounts of intertemporal choice have
`not included discussions of vividness, perhaps because vividness is not directly
`observable, its meaning is nevertheless intuitively comprehensible, and there
`are numerous examples of attempts to manipulate it.
`Drivers' education films depict the gruesome consequences of car accidents
`in an effort to make those consequences more vivid to young (and presumably
`myopic) drivers. But facts and statistics and even photographs of accidents have
`only a limited impact. Faced with continuing high accident rates among young
`drivers, several school districts have taken more drastic measures. A device
`intended to demonstrate the violence of even a low-speed collision has been
`put into use in several school districts. Students are accelerated down a
`ramp on a wheeled chair which, after gaining a speed of 5 miles per hour, is
`abruptly halted. It is difficult to understand this device in purely informational
`terms. Rather, the intention is to give immediate emotional significance to an
`otherwise abstract outcome. An analogous attempt to counter youthful myopia
`through manipulation of vividness is depicted in the documentary movie
`'Scared Straight', in which high-school students thought to be at risk of future
`delinquency toured a maximum security prison, were harassed by inmates, and
`were given as vivid an image of prison life as is possible without actually being
`locked up.
`While the accident simulator and the visit to the prison were aimed at youth,
`such efforts are not limited to teenagers. For example, a recent television
`advertisement for a supplementary retirement plan showed a young couple in
`the first frame opting not to participate in the plan, and then showed them
`physically ageing against a backdrop of increasing poverty. Each of these efforts
`at persuasion can be viewed as attempts to decrease ac so as to raise dread and
`enhance evaluation of the future consequences of current actions.
`
`Estimation of Discount Rates
`The sensitivity of intertemporal choice behaviour to savouring and dread
`suggests that the standard model may be mis-specified, leading to systematic
`bias in the estimation of discount rates. Since DU does not ordinarily
`incorporate savouring or dread, and since both of these factors attenuate
`
`IPR2020-00963
`Sony EX1011 Page 11
`
`

`

`676
`[SEPTEMBER
`JOURNAL
`THE ECONOMIC
`devaluation, conventional estimates of discount rates should be biased down-
`ward, especially in situations where savouring or dread significantly affect
`devaluation. As demonstrated, these include situations in which future out-
`comes are fleeting or can be vividly imagined. Also, savouring and dread exert
`their greatest impact at short and moderate time delays, so discount rates
`estimated from short-term trade-offs will tend to be more biased than rates
`estimated from long-term trade-offs.
`The bias in estimation of discount rates will be especially serious if savouring
`and dread are different for different categories of consumption. If this were the
`case, then the general assumption that 'the discount rate is independent of the
`category of consumption goods for which it is calculated' (Landsberger, I97I,
`p. I35I) would be invalid. Thus, for example, Hausman, in his I979 study,
`implicitly assumed that discount rates imputed from air-conditioner purchases
`would also apply to other intertemporal trade-offs. What he failed to consider
`was the possibility that air conditioners or other energy-using appliances have
`special characteristics that promote steep discounting. Monthly payments for
`electricity are spread over time and made less salient by being combined with
`pre-existing electrical charges, leading to the prediction of high devaluing even
`when time discounting is low. In contrast, purchase cost is immediate and
`lump-sum. This myopia-inducing quality of fuel- or electricity-consuming
`durables seems to have been recognised by various agencies of government that
`require efficiency ratings for appliances, and estimates of fuel consumption and
`yearly operating costs, to be affixed to new cars.
`
`Savings Behaviour
`The concepts of savouring and dread may help to explain the anomalous
`observation that - rather than dissaving following retirement (as is predicted
`by the permanent income and life-cycle theories of saving) - individuals
`typically increase their rate of saving following retirement and continue to
`amass increasing amounts of wealth until they die. A number of explanations
`have been offered for this phenomenon, including uncertain life expectancy
`is that
`and bequest motives.4 Another explanation offered by Moore (1978)
`individuals derive utility from wealth itself. The current model bolsters Moore's
`account by providing a reason why wealth may be a source of utility.
`Accumulations of wealth can constitute, in effect, a 'licence to savour' - i.e. to
`imagine and thus derive immediate pleasure from the consumption which the
`wealth could finance.
`But the theory also provides a second, perhaps even more plausible,
`explanation for the observed failure to dissave following retirement. Retirement
`for the young is a non-vivid event - perhaps partly because thinking about
`old age is aversive and tends to be avoided (resulting in a small a). Young
`middle-aged couples and individuals, possibly for this reason, often 'live like
`there's no tomorrow'. As retirement approaches, however, the prospect of
`having inadequate funds for retirement becomes increasingly vivid and causes
`
`4 For a recent summary of this debate see Modigliani (I986).
`
`IPR2020-00963
`Sony EX1011 Page 12
`
`

`

`677
`I987]
`CONSUMPTION
`OF DELAYED
`VALUATION
`anxiety, anxiety that can be allayed in part by stepping up savings. The onset
`of retirement itself, and the sudden loss of wage income, of course, greatly
`increases this anxiety for the future. This an

This document is available on Docket Alarm but you must sign up to view it.


Or .

Accessing this document will incur an additional charge of $.

After purchase, you can access this document again without charge.

Accept $ Charge
throbber

Still Working On It

This document is taking longer than usual to download. This can happen if we need to contact the court directly to obtain the document and their servers are running slowly.

Give it another minute or two to complete, and then try the refresh button.

throbber

A few More Minutes ... Still Working

It can take up to 5 minutes for us to download a document if the court servers are running slowly.

Thank you for your continued patience.

This document could not be displayed.

We could not find this document within its docket. Please go back to the docket page and check the link. If that does not work, go back to the docket and refresh it to pull the newest information.

Your account does not support viewing this document.

You need a Paid Account to view this document. Click here to change your account type.

Your account does not support viewing this document.

Set your membership status to view this document.

With a Docket Alarm membership, you'll get a whole lot more, including:

  • Up-to-date information for this case.
  • Email alerts whenever there is an update.
  • Full text search for other cases.
  • Get email alerts whenever a new case matches your search.

Become a Member

One Moment Please

The filing “” is large (MB) and is being downloaded.

Please refresh this page in a few minutes to see if the filing has been downloaded. The filing will also be emailed to you when the download completes.

Your document is on its way!

If you do not receive the document in five minutes, contact support at support@docketalarm.com.

Sealed Document

We are unable to display this document, it may be under a court ordered seal.

If you have proper credentials to access the file, you may proceed directly to the court's system using your government issued username and password.


Access Government Site

We are redirecting you
to a mobile optimized page.





Document Unreadable or Corrupt

Refresh this Document
Go to the Docket

We are unable to display this document.

Refresh this Document
Go to the Docket